• About
  • Contact
  • Staff
  • Home
  • Essays
  • Forum
  • Podcasts
  • Book Reviews
  • Liberty Classics

February 4, 2019|constitutional patriotism, European Union, Immanuel Kant, Jean-Claude Juncker, Jürgen Habermas, liberal constitutionalism, Nationalism

The Crumbling Anti-Politics of Constitutional Patriotism

by Samuel Gregg|

The Paul-Henri Spaak Building, home of the European Parliament in Brussels, Belgium (Image: artjazz/shutterstock.com).

 

If there’s anything that political earthquakes like Brexit and the ongoing spread of nationalist feeling throughout the European Union demonstrates, it’s that popular support for Europe’s integration project is floundering. In early 2018, France’s pro-EU president Emmanuel Macron publicly acknowledged that France would probably vote to leave the EU if given a simple in/out choice. Politics in a once stalwartly pro-EU nation like Italy is now dominated by Eurosceptic parties.

Advocates for deeper European integration like German chancellor Angela Merkel seldom pass up chances to insist, as she did in a November 2018 speech, that “Nation-states should be willing to give up their sovereignty today.” Many Europeans undoubtedly continue to favor the EU’s commercial conveniences. But outside an increasingly-isolated political class which dominates ever-weakening establishment political parties, vocal enthusiasts for a supranational European state are becoming scarce.

The reasons for this vary. They range from the pervasive association of the EU with unaccountable bureaucracies, to the contempt with which European Commission President Jean-Claude Juncker regards anyone questioning his “more-Europe-means-more-EU” program.

There is, however, a lesser-known factor at work which merits greater attention. This concerns the failure of what’s called “constitutional patriotism” to generate the type of widespread attachment to the EU by ordinary Europeans that’s capable of matching the way in which, for example, Poles are invested in the idea of Poland or many French citizens’ ongoing-connectedness to their nation.

It’s All About Germany

Though there are several versions of constitutional patriotism in Europe, they are all traceable to the German philosopher Immanuel Kant’s book, Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch (1795). This proposed the development of a federation of republican states whose growing integration would promote international cooperation, war’s eventual eradication, and even a type of world citizenship.

But constitutional patriotism’s more immediate origins lie, like so many contemporary European problems, in the desire to heal particular traumas of German history. One such wound is the failure of the revolutions which swept Europe in 1848 to establish lasting liberal regimes in Germany and throughout the continent more generally

Historian after historian has illustrated that the eventual defeat of these revolutions—often revealingly referred to as “the Spring of Nations”—owes much to the fact that they were liberal and nationalist in character. Prominent 1848 revolutionaries like Giuseppe Mazzini, Lajos Kossuth, and Heinrich von Gagern were liberals and Italian, Hungarian and German nationalists respectively.

The nationalist sentiments that generated popular support for the 1848 revolutions meant that many revolutionary leaders found themselves having to choose between promoting liberal constitutional principles like equality of all before the law, or advancing their people’s aspirations to establish ethnically-homogenous nations. Time and again, nationalist priorities trumped liberal principles.

Consider the 1848 liberal revolutions in the German-speaking states. One of their goals was to unify these entities into a single German nation-state. Even after their revolutions were crushed in 1849, German liberals remained committed to this objective. This helps explain why many of them went from fiercely opposing Otto von Bismarck when the arch-conservative was appointed Prussian Chancellor in 1862, to being fervent supporters of Bismarck’s unification of Germany via the Prussian army’s victories over the Austrian Empire in 1866 and France in 1870.

It was thus “blood and iron,” to recall Bismarck’s famous 1862 speech, which realized German unification—not peaceful elections and the negotiations of enlightened politicians. Yet this didn’t prevent many German liberals from enthusiastically celebrating and the new and rather un-liberal German Empire and becoming some of its strongest supporters.

Worries about the mesmerizing effects of national feeling upon Germans were only exacerbated by the interwar liberal Weimar Republic’s failure to restrain German nationalism or prevent it from acquiring National Socialism’s racialist flavor. The ensuing catastrophe which befell Germany reinforced many postwar German intellectuals’ determination to establish a liberal regime grounded upon very different attitudes. Herein lies constitutional patriotism’s immediate genesis.

Habermas’ World

The German scholar most associated with constitutional patriotism is the philosopher Jürgen Habermas. The disaster of two World Wars and the crimes committed by German nationals and the German state in the name of the German Volk between 1933 and 1945 made it imperative, he argued, that Germany disavow any strong emphasis upon ethnic-homogeneity. Habermas’ constitutional patriotism sought to ground political regimes upon affection for what he called more “abstract” principles. By this, he meant things like democratic methods, civic commitment, tolerance, and openness. Above all, Habermas had in mind “a consensus on the procedure for the legitimate enactment of laws and the legitimate exercise of power.”

It’s not hard to comprehend why such ideas gained traction in Germany after World War II and the moral cataclysm of the Holocaust. It’s also easy to understand how Habermasian constitutional patriotism became seen as a way to legitimize the European integration project.

After all, constitutional patriotism is all about transcending national differences—indeed, any strong political disagreements. Its emphasis isn’t just upon participation, the development of consensus, etc. Constitutional patriotism also involves fostering doubts about any positive allegiances, such as those generated by religion or ethnicity, which might dilute commitment to constitutional patriotism’s “thinner” norms.

Constitutional patriotism’s objective is thus to defang the nation-state. The ultimate goal is to gradually replace it with a supranational cosmopolitan entity by progressively detaching people from their national memories and collapsing politics into a complicated web of procedures.

One example of how this occurs is the most recent iteration of the EU’s legal character. Signed in 2007, the Treaty of Lisbon refers, like many constitutions, to general principles like liberty and justice. It also mentions a political, cultural and religious backdrop to European unification, but only fleetingly. Hundreds of years of the rich pluralist histories of multiple European peoples are thus reduced to almost as a side-note.

Normatively-speaking, the Lisbon Treaty gets far more specific when it speaks of the EU promoting “peace, security, the sustainable development of the Earth, solidarity and mutual respect among peoples, free and fair trade, eradication of poverty,” etc. All this has a mildly utopian ring to it. The effect, however, is to identify certain universals to which nobody could strongly object as things which Europeans must treat seriously if they truly want to be world citizens but whose meaning remains elastic enough not to excite people’s passions.

Then there is the Treaty’s relentless concentration upon procedures: which EU institution is competent to do what; how consultative mechanisms should work; the means by why people are appointed to various positions; who is to be included in what part of multi-leveled decision-making processes, etc.

To some degree, all constitutions do this. But there is an underlying imperative driving the Treaty’s procedural emphases. This is the forging of agreement by diluting, if not actively discouraging, expressions of strong dissension, especially those which arise outside officially-approved channels. It adds up not to a vision of a Europe of nations, but rather the formation of a vast administrative state undergirded by relatively thin moral commitments and controlled by those who have mastered its complicated decision-making procedures: i.e., a transnational and professional political-bureaucratic class.

You Can’t Build Something on Nothing

The last century of European history makes constitutional patriotism’s attractiveness comprehensible. Who wouldn’t want to see the establishment of political regimes capable of banishing forever the prospect of yet another inter-European configuration?

The shoals upon which Europe’s experiment with constitutional patriotism founders today are twofold.

First, constitutional patriotism is in many ways anti-political. Among other things, politics involves the articulation of conflicting, often irreconcilable views on topics as varied as life’s meaning to the state’s economic role. Constitutional patriotism tries to minimize, if not marginalize such debates altogether.

But such disagreements are part of the human condition. Efforts to extinguish procedurally the articulation of powerful political allegiances or to stigmatize widespread dissent are therefore bound to provoke anger with those people and institutions doing the suppressing or branding. In that sense, constitutional patriotism actually facilitates political conflicts by virtue of trying to repress them.

Second, constitutional patriotism hasn’t proved capable of undermining millions of Europeans’ conviction that they do belong to specific ethnic-linguistic communities with long, complicated and distinct histories. To be Dutch, French, Scottish, Hungarian, Flemish, Polish, Finnish or Greek continues to mean very concrete, specific things to millions of people in the Netherlands, France, Scotland, Hungary, and so forth. Moreover, they care much more about these realties than they do about “communication,” “trust in procedures,” or “shared modalities of practical action,” to use prominent buzzwords of constitutional patriotism.

That doesn’t necessarily mean that these Europeans don’t value liberal constitutionalism. Its roots are, after all, distinctly European. Nevertheless it does indicate that constitutional patriotism’s attempts to dilute national memories and replace them with a difference-repressing proceduralism overlain with a content-light universalistic rhetoric is guaranteed to provoke deep dissatisfaction.

National Feeling and Liberal Constitutionalism Aren’t Incompatible

The irony is that there isn’t any necessary incompatibility between a strong national identity and a commitment to liberal constitutionalism. One example is the United States. When American soldiers swear to support and defend the U.S. Constitution, they’re certainly promising to defend a constitutional system of laws. But we also know that they are also undertaking to defend a specific nation that emerged out of a particular interplay of historical events and ideas and which is composed of people with whom they share these distinct national ties.

It makes no difference that some of those people were born in the United States while others are newly-minted citizens who legally migrated to America ten years ago from South America. A historically-specific national identity and a constitutional system that emphasizes liberty and rule of law are so intertwined in many Americans’ minds that it’s hard for them to conceptualize one without the other.

By contrast, much of Europe is rapidly heading in the opposite direction. Bolstering the nation-state is increasingly seen by many Europeans as the only way to defend their freedoms and cherished cultural particularities from supranational politicians who increasingly denounce any strong expression of national identity as crypto-racism and deride those who value national sovereignty as proto-fascists.

The more, however, that post-national identity advocates like Juncker, Macron or Merkel try advancing cosmopolitan patriotism over and against national feeling, the greater grows the chasm between liberal constitutionalism and national patriotism. That not only risks deepening the already-yawning gap between Europe’s rulers and the ruled. It also heightens the possibility of reigniting some of the passions which, in the past, tore Europe asunder.

Put another way, without the genuine patriotism which arises from deep attachment to national distinctiveness, liberal constitutionalism risks collapsing into mere functionalism and sentimental do-gooder humanitarianism. But without liberal constitutionalism, patriotism can easily degenerate into mere chauvinism.

Plainly, this isn’t an easy balance to strike. But if European nations can’t do so, I can guarantee one thing: that all of us will be experiencing some very sharp after-effects in the near future.

Samuel Gregg

Samuel Gregg is research director at the Acton Institute.

About the Author

“Slouching Towards Mar-a-Lago:” A Conversation with Andrew Bacevich
Solzhenitsyn in Exile

Recent Popular Posts

  • Popular
  • Today Week Month All
  • The Gresham's Law of Law February 13, 2018
  • Crisis of the Calhoun United March 20, 2013
  • Jury Nullification: Good or Bad? January 16, 2018
  • Lessons of the French Revolution February 20, 2020
  • Jacques Lacan: Conservative Icon? January 17, 2018
Ajax spinner

Related Posts

Related

Book Reviews

A Mirror of the 20th-Century Congress

by Joseph Postell

Wright undermined the very basis of his local popularity—the decentralized nature of the House—by supporting reforms that gave power to the party leaders.

Read More

The Graces of Flannery O'Connor

by Henry T. Edmondson III

O’Connor’s correspondence is a goldmine of piercing insight and startling reflections on everything from literature to philosophy to raising peacocks.

Read More

Liberty Classics

Rereading Politica in the Post-Liberal Moment

by Glenn A. Moots

Althusius offers a rich constitutionalism that empowers persons to thrive alongside one another in deliberate communities.

Read More

James Fenimore Cooper and the American Experiment

by Melissa Matthes

In The American Democrat, James Fenimore Cooper defended democracy against both mob rule and majority tyranny.

Read More

Podcasts

Stuck With Decadence

A discussion with Ross Douthat

Ross Douthat discusses with Richard Reinsch his new book The Decadent Society.

Read More

Can the Postmodern Natural Law Remedy Our Failing Humanism?

A discussion with Graham McAleer

Graham McAleer discusses how postmodern natural law can help us think more coherently about human beings and our actions.

Read More

Did the Civil Rights Constitution Distort American Politics?

A discussion with Christopher Caldwell

Christopher Caldwell discusses his new book, The Age of Entitlement.

Read More

America, Land of Deformed Institutions

A discussion with Yuval Levin

Yuval Levin pinpoints that American alienation and anger emerges from our weak political, social, and religious institutions.

Read More

Recent Posts

  • The Just Restraint of the Vicious

    For some contemporary criminal justice reformers, devotion to ideology leads to illogical conclusions about human nature and character change.
    by Gerard T. Mundy

  • Too Immature to be Punished?

    When I look back on my own life, I think I knew by the age of ten that one should not strangle old ladies in their beds.
    by Theodore Dalrymple

  • A Badge of Discrimination

    The British National Health Service has spoken: Wear the badge or declare yourself to be a bigot.
    by Theodore Dalrymple

  • A Judicial Takeover of Asylum Policy?

    Thuraissigiam threatens to make both the law and the facts in every petition for asylum—and there are thousands of them—a matter for the courts.
    by Thomas Ascik

  • The Environmental Uncertainty Principle

    By engaging in such flagrant projection, the Times has highlighted once again the problem with groupthink in the climate discussion.
    by Paul Schwennesen

Blogroll

  • Acton PowerBlog
  • Cafe Hayek
  • Cato@Liberty
  • Claremont
  • Congress Shall Make No Law
  • EconLog
  • Fed Soc Blog
  • First Things
  • Hoover
  • ISI First Principles Journal
  • Legal Theory Blog
  • Marginal Revolution
  • Pacific Legal Liberty Blog
  • Point of Law
  • Power Line
  • Professor Bainbridge
  • Ricochet
  • Right Reason
  • Spengler
  • The American
  • The Beacon Blog
  • The Foundry
  • The Originalism Blog
  • The Public Discourse
  • University Bookman
  • Via Meadia
  • Volokh

Archives

  • All Posts & Publications
  • Book Reviews
  • Liberty Forum
  • Liberty Law Blog
  • Liberty Law Talk

About

Law & Liberty’s focus is on the classical liberal tradition of law and political thought and how it shapes a society of free and responsible persons. This site brings together serious debate, commentary, essays, book reviews, interviews, and educational material in a commitment to the first principles of law in a free society. Law & Liberty considers a range of foundational and contemporary legal issues, legal philosophy, and pedagogy.

The opinions expressed on Law & Liberty are solely those of the contributors to the site and do not reflect the opinions of Liberty Fund.
  • Home
  • About
  • Staff
  • Contact
  • Archive

© 2021 Liberty Fund, Inc.

This site uses local and third-party cookies to analyze traffic. If you want to know more, click here.
By closing this banner or clicking any link in this page, you agree with this practice.Accept Read More
Privacy & Cookies Policy
Necessary Always Enabled

Subscribe
Get Law and Liberty's latest content delivered to you daily
  • This field is for validation purposes and should be left unchanged.
Close